Robert Kraynak: "Catholicism and the Declaration ..." Part IV
A fourth source of the American political tradition is the classical
republican tradition-the inheritance of Greece and Rome. ... [T]here were considerable rhetorical appeals to classical themes, especially to comparisons between the
ancient Roman republic and the modern American republic. For
example, the founders spoke repeatedly of republican virtue and
classical moral virtues; George Washington was depicted in the image
of Cinncinatus (the Roman farmer-general who served his country in
war and returned to his farm); the anti-Federalists appealed to the
small republic model for their idea of liberty and referred to
themselves as Brutus and Cato; the authors of The Federalist called
themselves Publius (after Publius Publicola, a Roman freedom fighter
who helped to overthrow kingship and establish the Roman republic);
and the architectural style of Washington, D.C. was modeled on
classical Rome, with Capitol Hill named after Capitoline Hill and the
Supreme Court building modeled on a pagan temple.
[O]ne must also
recognize the fundamental difference between ancient and modern
republicanism-the Roman republic was governed by a Senate made up
of a hereditary aristocracy of patricians or "enrolled fathers" whose
primary occupations were politics, war, and imperial conquest. The
American republic drew its authority from the sovereign people and
was intended to be a commercial republic rather than a military
republic. The contrast with ancient Rome becomes even clearer when
the fifth and sixth elements of the American tradition are described.
The fifth element is the natural rights-social contract theory,
proclaimed in the Declaration of Independence as well as in other
writings before and after the American Revolution. The basic idea of
natural rights is that all men are created equal in the sense of being
endowed by the Creator with equal rights to life, liberty, and the
pursuit of happiness. These rights are natural and inalienable because
they were put into human nature by God ("Nature's God") and cannot
be taken away by other men or by states. Governments exist to secure
those rights, and they do this best when they are based on the consent
of the people. Revolution is justified when natural rights are violated by
a series of abuses or when the consent of the governed is thwarted by
serious usurpations of power. This is essentially Lockean social contract
theory, and some of the language in the second paragraph of the
Declaration referring to "a long train of abuses" is directly copied from chapter nineteen of john Locke's Second Treatise of Government, "Of the
Dissolution of Government."
The reliance on Locke, of course, does not mean that the Declaration
is exclusively Lockean. As Walter Nicgorski points out, there are nonLockean
features in the Declaration drawn from the classical and
Christian traditions. Jefferson himself referred to a mixture of
elements when he described the document as "an expression of the
American mind" drawn from common ideas of the time as well as from
"the elementary books of public right [by] Aristotle, Cicero, Locke,
Sidney, etc." (Letter of Jefferson to Henry Lee, May 8, 1825). This
mixture can be seen in the three main sections of the Declaration: I,
The statement of general principles, based on the law of nature aad
nature's God; II, The statement of 27 grievances against the King and
British Parliament; and III, The proclamation of freedom and
independence from Great Britain.
In the famous first section, Locke's influence predominates in the
general principles of God-given natural rights, government by consent,
and the right to revolution that I summarized above. Some scholars
have also detected the influence of Emer de Vattel's The Law of Nations
in the opening lines, where the principles are applied to relations
among nations ("when in the course of human events, it becomes
necessary for one people to dissolve the political bands which have
connected them with another ... "). The suggestion is that the
Declaration is primarily a document of international law, asserting the
corporate right of one people or nation to self-determination like the
other peoples and nations of the world. This insight, of course, does not negate the Lockean features of the document; it merely qualifies them
by bringing out the concern for national self-determination or
corporate self-government in addition to individual rights.
Locke's influence is also qualified in the central section of the
Declaration where the grievances against the King and British
Parliament are listed to justify the Revolution. ... Many of these grievances (as noted above)
were based on the traditional rights and privileges of Englishmen
derived from English common law, although many also overlap with
Locke's list of legitimate grievances against tyrannical government
found in chapter nineteen of The Second Treatise of Government .... The list of grievances in the
Declaration thus appears to be a blend of Lockean and English common
law principles.
The third and last section of the Declaration insists on the necessity
of the colonies to become free and independent states-to be selfgoverning
peoples who legislate for themselves-despite the ties of
kinship and blood ("consanguinity") between American colonists and
Englishmen. This section of the Declaration ends with appeals to divine
Providence and with pledges of honor to aid in the success of their
revolutionary cause. Like other parts of the document, these
sentiments also seem to be a blend of the English heritage, the
Christian notion of a providential God, the gentlemen's code of honor,
and classical republican ideas of patriotic duty to participate in politics
and even to sacrifice one's life for one's country. The Declaration is
thus a subtle and complex weaving of the Lockean and non-Lockean
elements in the American political tradition.
The main omission in the Declaration of Independence is any
reference to the new form of government that the Americans should
adopt-the assumption being that it is a matter left open for
deliberation and trial and error after the Revolution. As we know, this
decision was settled a decade later when Americans adopted the U.S. Constitution and became a Federal Republic or a "natural rights
republic" (to use Michael Zuckert's apt phrase). As James Madison
argued, the social basis of the American republic would be a
multiplicity of interest groups arising in a large or extensive
commercial society in which property rights would be protected from
an overbearing majority. Madison also argued that the protections for
liberty and the common good could not be based on the assumption
that "enlightened statesmen will always be at the helm." While
recognizing the need for virtue and patriotism, he specifically said that
the surest protection for liberty would be a set of checks and balances
that divided the powers of government into many competing centers.
The separation of powers and a multiplicity of economic interest
groups would thus be the main features of Madisonian
constitutionalism, rather than reliance on the wisdom and patriotism
of leaders and citizens.
No comments:
Post a Comment